A gambling strategy where the amount is raised until a person wins or becomes insolvent
A martingale is a class of 👏 betting strategies that originated from and were popular in 18th-century France. The simplest of these strategies was designed for a 👏 game in which the gambler wins the stake if a coin comes up heads and loses if it comes up 👏 tails. The strategy had the gambler double the bet after every loss, so that the first win would recover all 👏 previous losses plus win a profit equal to the original stake. Thus the strategy is an instantiation of the St. 👏 Petersburg paradox.
Since a gambler will almost surely eventually flip heads, the martingale betting strategy is certain to make money for 👏 the gambler provided they have infinite wealth and there is no limit on money earned in a single bet. However, 👏 no gambler has infinite wealth, and the exponential growth of the bets can bankrupt unlucky gamblers who choose to use 👏 the martingale, causing a catastrophic loss. Despite the fact that the gambler usually wins a small net reward, thus appearing 👏 to have a sound strategy, the gambler's expected value remains zero because the small probability that the gambler will suffer 👏 a catastrophic loss exactly balances with the expected gain. In a casino, the expected value is negative, due to the 👏 house's edge. Additionally, as the likelihood of a string of consecutive losses is higher than common intuition suggests, martingale strategies 👏 can bankrupt a gambler quickly.
The martingale strategy has also been applied to roulette, as the probability of hitting either red 👏 or black is close to 50%.
Intuitive analysis [ edit ]
The fundamental reason why all martingale-type betting systems fail is that 👏 no amount of information about the results of past bets can be used to predict the results of a future 👏 bet with accuracy better than chance. In mathematical terminology, this corresponds to the assumption that the win–loss outcomes of each 👏 bet are independent and identically distributed random variables, an assumption which is valid in many realistic situations. It follows from 👏 this assumption that the expected value of a series of bets is equal to the sum, over all bets that 👏 could potentially occur in the series, of the expected value of a potential bet times the probability that the player 👏 will make that bet. In most casino games, the expected value of any individual bet is negative, so the sum 👏 of many negative numbers will also always be negative.
The martingale strategy fails even with unbounded stopping time, as long as 👏 there is a limit on earnings or on the bets (which is also true in practice).[1] It is only with 👏 unbounded wealth, bets and time that it could be argued that the martingale becomes a winning strategy.
Mathematical analysis [ edit 👏 ]
The impossibility of winning over the long run, given a limit of the size of bets or a limit in 👏 the size of one's bankroll or line of credit, is proven by the optional stopping theorem.[1]
However, without these limits, the 👏 martingale betting strategy is certain to make money for the gambler because the chance of at least one coin flip 👏 coming up heads approaches one as the number of coin flips approaches infinity.
Mathematical analysis of a single round [ edit 👏 ]
Let one round be defined as a sequence of consecutive losses followed by either a win, or bankruptcy of the 👏 gambler. After a win, the gambler "resets" and is considered to have started a new round. A continuous sequence of 👏 martingale bets can thus be partitioned into a sequence of independent rounds. Following is an analysis of the expected value 👏 of one round.
Let q be the probability of losing (e.g. for American double-zero roulette, it is 20/38 for a bet 👏 on black or red). Let B be the amount of the initial bet. Let n be the finite number of 👏 bets the gambler can afford to lose.
The probability that the gambler will lose all n bets is qn. When all 👏 bets lose, the total loss is
∑ i = 1 n B ⋅ 2 i − 1 = B ( 2 👏 n − 1 ) {\displaystyle \sum _{i=1}^{n}B\cdot 2^{i-1}=B(2^{n}-1)}
The probability the gambler does not lose all n bets is 1 − 👏 qn. In all other cases, the gambler wins the initial bet (B.) Thus, the expected profit per round is
( 1 👏 − q n ) ⋅ B − q n ⋅ B ( 2 n − 1 ) = B ( 👏 1 − ( 2 q ) n ) {\displaystyle (1-q^{n})\cdot B-q^{n}\cdot B(2^{n}-1)=B(1-(2q)^{n})}
Whenever q > 1/2, the expression 1 − (2q)n 👏 < 0 for all n > 0. Thus, for all games where a gambler is more likely to lose than 👏 to win any given bet, that gambler is expected to lose money, on average, each round. Increasing the size of 👏 wager for each round per the martingale system only serves to increase the average loss.
Suppose a gambler has a 63-unit 👏 gambling bankroll. The gambler might bet 1 unit on the first spin. On each loss, the bet is doubled. Thus, 👏 taking k as the number of preceding consecutive losses, the player will always bet 2k units.
With a win on any 👏 given spin, the gambler will net 1 unit over the total amount wagered to that point. Once this win is 👏 achieved, the gambler restarts the system with a 1 unit bet.
With losses on all of the first six spins, the 👏 gambler loses a total of 63 units. This exhausts the bankroll and the martingale cannot be continued.
In this example, the 👏 probability of losing the entire bankroll and being unable to continue the martingale is equal to the probability of 6 👏 consecutive losses: (10/19)6 = 2.1256%. The probability of winning is equal to 1 minus the probability of losing 6 times: 👏 1 − (10/19)6 = 97.8744%.
The expected amount won is (1 × 0.978744) = 0.978744.
The expected amount lost is (63 × 👏 0.021256)= 1.339118.
Thus, the total expected value for each application of the betting system is (0.978744 − 1.339118) = −0.360374 .
In 👏 a unique circumstance, this strategy can make sense. Suppose the gambler possesses exactly 63 units but desperately needs a total 👏 of 64. Assuming q > 1/2 (it is a real casino) and he may only place bets at even odds, 👏 his best strategy is bold play: at each spin, he should bet the smallest amount such that if he wins 👏 he reaches his target immediately, and if he does not have enough for this, he should simply bet everything. Eventually 👏 he either goes bust or reaches his target. This strategy gives him a probability of 97.8744% of achieving the goal 👏 of winning one unit vs. a 2.1256% chance of losing all 63 units, and that is the best probability possible 👏 in this circumstance.[2] However, bold play is not always the optimal strategy for having the biggest possible chance to increase 👏 an initial capital to some desired higher amount. If the gambler can bet arbitrarily small amounts at arbitrarily long odds 👏 (but still with the same expected loss of 10/19 of the stake at each bet), and can only place one 👏 bet at each spin, then there are strategies with above 98% chance of attaining his goal, and these use very 👏 timid play unless the gambler is close to losing all his capital, in which case he does switch to extremely 👏 bold play.[3]
Alternative mathematical analysis [ edit ]
The previous analysis calculates expected value, but we can ask another question: what is 👏 the chance that one can play a casino game using the martingale strategy, and avoid the losing streak long enough 👏 to double one's bankroll?
As before, this depends on the likelihood of losing 6 roulette spins in a row assuming we 👏 are betting red/black or even/odd. Many gamblers believe that the chances of losing 6 in a row are remote, and 👏 that with a patient adherence to the strategy they will slowly increase their bankroll.
In reality, the odds of a streak 👏 of 6 losses in a row are much higher than many people intuitively believe. Psychological studies have shown that since 👏 people know that the odds of losing 6 times in a row out of 6 plays are low, they incorrectly 👏 assume that in a longer string of plays the odds are also very low. In fact, while the chance of 👏 losing 6 times in a row in 6 plays is a relatively low 1.8% on a single-zero wheel, the probability 👏 of losing 6 times in a row (i.e. encountering a streak of 6 losses) at some point during a string 👏 of 200 plays is approximately 84%. Even if the gambler can tolerate betting ~1,000 times their original bet, a streak 👏 of 10 losses in a row has an ~11% chance of occurring in a string of 200 plays. Such a 👏 loss streak would likely wipe out the bettor, as 10 consecutive losses using the martingale strategy means a loss of 👏 1,023x the original bet.
These unintuitively risky probabilities raise the bankroll requirement for "safe" long-term martingale betting to infeasibly high numbers. 👏 To have an under 10% chance of failing to survive a long loss streak during 5,000 plays, the bettor must 👏 have enough to double their bets for 15 losses. This means the bettor must have over 65,500 (2^15-1 for their 👏 15 losses and 2^15 for their 16th streak-ending winning bet) times their original bet size. Thus, a player making 10 👏 unit bets would want to have over 655,000 units in their bankroll (and still have a ~5.5% chance of losing 👏 it all during 5,000 plays).
When people are asked to invent data representing 200 coin tosses, they often do not add 👏 streaks of more than 5 because they believe that these streaks are very unlikely.[4] This intuitive belief is sometimes referred 👏 to as the representativeness heuristic.
In a classic martingale betting style, gamblers increase bets after each loss in hopes that an 👏 eventual win will recover all previous losses. The anti-martingale approach, also known as the reverse martingale, instead increases bets after 👏 wins, while reducing them after a loss. The perception is that the gambler will benefit from a winning streak or 👏 a "hot hand", while reducing losses while "cold" or otherwise having a losing streak. As the single bets are independent 👏 from each other (and from the gambler's expectations), the concept of winning "streaks" is merely an example of gambler's fallacy, 👏 and the anti-martingale strategy fails to make any money.
If on the other hand, real-life stock returns are serially correlated (for 👏 instance due to economic cycles and delayed reaction to news of larger market participants), "streaks" of wins or losses do 👏 happen more often and are longer than those under a purely random process, the anti-martingale strategy could theoretically apply and 👏 can be used in trading systems (as trend-following or "doubling up"). This concept is similar to that used in momentum 👏 investing and some technical analysis investing strategies.
See also [ edit ]
Double or nothing – A decision in gambling that will 👏 either double ones losses or cancel them out
Escalation of commitment – A human behavior pattern in which the participant takes 👏 on increasingly greater risk
St. Petersburg paradox – Paradox involving a game with repeated coin flipping
Sunk cost fallacy – Cost that 👏 has already been incurred and cannot be recovered Pages displaying short descriptions of redirect targets